A5
Whether bodily and sensible pleasures are greater than spiritual and intellectual pleasures?
[a]
Objection 1: It would seem that bodily and sensible pleasures are greater than spiritual and intelligible pleasures.
For all men seek some pleasure, according to the Philosopher (Ethic. x, 2, 4).
But more seek sensible pleasures, than intelligible spiritual pleasures.
Therefore bodily pleasures are greater.
[b]
Objection 2: Further, the greatness of a cause is known by its effect.
But bodily pleasures have greater effects; since "they alter the state of the body, and in some they cause madness" (Ethic. vii, 3).
Therefore bodily pleasures are greater.
[c]
Objection 3: Further, bodily pleasures need to be tempered and checked, by reason of their vehemence: whereas there is no need to check spiritual pleasures.
Therefore bodily pleasures are greater.
[d]
On the contrary, It is written (Ps. 118:103): "How sweet are Thy words to my palate; more than honey to my mouth!"
And the Philosopher says (Ethic. x, 7) that "the greatest pleasure is derived from the operation of wisdom."
[e]
I answer that, As stated above [1265] (A [1]), pleasure arises from union with a suitable object perceived or known.
Now, in the operations of the soul, especially of the sensitive and intellectual soul, it must be noted that, since they do not pass into outward matter, they are acts or perfections of the agent, e. g. to understand, to feel, to will and the like: because actions which pass into outward matter, are actions and perfections rather of the matter transformed; for "movement is the act produced by the mover in the thing moved" (Phys. iii, 3).
Accordingly the aforesaid actions of the sensitive and intellectual soul, are themselves a certain good of the agent, and are known by sense and intellect.
Wherefore from them also does pleasure arise, and not only from their objects.
[f]
If therefore we compare intellectual pleasures with sensible pleasures, according as we delight in the very actions, for instance in sensitive and in intellectual knowledge; without doubt intellectual pleasures are much greater than sensible pleasures.
For man takes much more delight in knowing something, by understanding it, than in knowing something by perceiving it with his sense.
Because intellectual knowledge is more perfect; and because it is better known, since the intellect reflects on its own act more than sense does.
Moreover intellectual knowledge is more beloved: for there is no one who would not forfeit his bodily sight rather than his intellectual vision, as beasts or fools are deprived thereof, as Augustine says in De Civ. Dei (De Trin. xiv, 14).
[g]
If, however, intellectual spiritual pleasures be compared with sensible bodily pleasures, then, in themselves and absolutely speaking, spiritual pleasures are greater.
And this appears from the consideration of the three things needed for pleasure, viz. the good which is brought into conjunction, that to which it is conjoined, and the conjunction itself.
For spiritual good is both greater and more beloved than bodily good: a sign whereof is that men abstain from even the greatest bodily pleasures, rather than suffer loss of honor which is an intellectual good.
Likewise the intellectual faculty is much more noble and more knowing than the sensitive faculty.
Also the conjunction is more intimate, more perfect and more firm.
More intimate, because the senses stop at the outward accidents of a thing, whereas the intellect penetrates to the essence; for the object of the intellect is "what a thing is."
More perfect, because the conjunction of the sensible to the sense implies movement, which is an imperfect act: wherefore sensible pleasures are not perceived all at once, but some part of them is passing away, while some other part is looked forward to as yet to be realized, as is manifest in pleasures of the table and in sexual pleasures: whereas intelligible things are without movement: hence pleasures of this kind are realized all at once.
More firm; because the objects of bodily pleasure are corruptible, and soon pass away; whereas spiritual goods are incorruptible.
[h]
On the other hand, in relation to us, bodily pleasures are more vehement, for three reasons.
First, because sensible things are more known to us, than intelligible things.
Secondly, because sensible pleasures, through being passions of the sensitive appetite, are accompanied by some alteration in the body: whereas this does not occur in spiritual pleasures, save by reason of a certain reaction of the superior appetite on the lower.
Thirdly, because bodily pleasures are sought as remedies for bodily defects or troubles, whence various griefs arise.
Wherefore bodily pleasures, by reason of their succeeding griefs of this kind, are felt the more, and consequently are welcomed more than spiritual pleasures, which have no contrary griefs, as we shall state farther on ([1266] Q [35], A [5]).
[i]
Reply to Objection 1: The reason why more seek bodily pleasures is because sensible goods are known better and more generally: and, again, because men need pleasures as remedies for many kinds of sorrow and sadness: and since the majority cannot attain spiritual pleasures, which are proper to the virtuous, hence it is that they turn aside to seek those of the body.
[j]
Reply to Objection 2: Bodily transmutation arises more from bodily pleasures, inasmuch as they are passions of the sensitive appetite.
[k]
Reply to Objection 3: Bodily pleasures are realized in the sensitive faculty which is governed by reason: wherefore they need to be tempered and checked by reason.
But spiritual pleasures are in the mind, which is itself the rule: wherefore they are in themselves both sober and moderate.
|